ar X iv : g r - qc / 9 70 40 39 v 1 1 5 A pr 1 99 7 Against “ Against Many - Worlds Interpretations ”
نویسنده
چکیده
The paper entitled “Against Many-Worlds Interpretations” by A. Kent, which has recently been submitted to the e-Print archive (gr-qc/9703089) contained some misconceptions. The claims on Everett’s many-worlds interpretation are quoted and answered. 03.65.Bz Typeset using REVTEX 1 A. Kent has submitted the paper [1] entitled “Against Many-Worlds Interpretations”, in which we can see frequently (almost endlessly) raised claims on Everett’s many-worlds interpretation (MWI). However, these claims apparently came from misconceptions about Everett’s original MWI and I think we should correct them. The paper neither is intended for a debate on the different versions of MWIs, nor criticize recent post-Everettians view, such as consistent histories approach. I just show what the Everett MWI is. In the paper [1] (Subsection “A. Everett” in Section II. “THE CASE AGAINST”), the author tries to illustrate problems on the Everett MWI [2] by a simple example (typographic errors are corrected, all quotes appear in italics): Suppose that a previously polarized spin2 particle has just had its spin measured by a macroscopic Stern-Gerlach device, on an axis chosen so that the probability of measuring spin + 2 is 2 3 . The result can be idealized by the wavefunction φ = a φ0 ⊗ Φ0 + b φ1 ⊗ Φ1 (2) where φ0 is the spin + 1 2 state of the particle, Φ0 the state of the device having measured spin + 2 ; φ1, Φ1 likewise correspond to spin − 1 2 ; |a| = 2 3 , |b| = 1 3 . Now in trying to interpret this result we encounter the following problems: . . . First of all, the above wavefunction does not describe any quantum-mechanical measurement process which is distinguished from the classical one by the occurrence of the collapse-ofwavefunction (COW) phenomenon. It simply describes a state after the interaction between the spin and the Stern-Gerlach device occurred. Quantum mechanics cannot contradict with the above description, even the Copenhagen interpretation agrees with until an observation by an observer takes place [3]. In Everett’s MWI, it is essential to consider an observer state, in which all physical informations which were observed by the observer are embedded. Therefore, the above equation should be replaced by φ = a φ0 ⊗ Φ0 ⊗Ψ0 + b φ1 ⊗ Φ1 ⊗Ψ1 (2a) 2 where, Ψ0 and Ψ1 denote the observer states who observed the spin + 1 2 and − 2 respectively. This is a direct consequence of (A) the linearity of the time evolution operator U(t) which includes the interaction between the object and observer systems and of (B) the relation which should be satisfied if the object system is prepared in the eigenstates φi and the observer system is prepared to observe the observable (the spin component): U(t)φi ⊗ Φi ⊗Ψ = φi ⊗ Φi ⊗Ψi. (2b) The author continues: Firstly, no choice of basis has been specified; we could expand φ in the 1dimensional basis {φ} or any of the orthogonal 2-dimensional bases {cos θ φ0 ⊗ Φ0 + sin θ φ1 ⊗ Φ1, sin θ φ0 ⊗ Φ0 − cos θ φ1 ⊗ Φ1} (3) or indeed in multi-dimensional or unorthogonal bases. Of course, the information is in the wavefunction is basis-independent, and one is free to choose any particular basis to work with. But if one intends to make a physical interpretation only in one particular basis, using quantities (such as |a| and |b|) which are defined by that basis, one needs to define this process (and, in particular, the preferred basis) by an axiom. This Everett fails to do. The author apparently fails in understanding what the Everett MWI is. As stated above, Eq. (2) by itself tells nothing about what was observed by an observer unless we specify the observer. In the state (2a), we can see that there are two observer states Ψ0 and Ψ1, each of which is evolved from the same observer state Ψ as shown in Eq. (2b). These two observer states correspond to the two observers seeing different outcomes, i.e., spin+ 2 and spin2 . There is no objective COW, but it appears to the observer that the state of the object system has collapsed into one of the eigenstates of the observable, while the whole system which includes the observer system is still in a superposition. This is the Everett MWI. 3 We do not have to require any loss of coherence between the branched states: The process described by Eq. (2b), in which there is no room for indicating any kind of decoherence, defines the observer states unambiguously. This is why there is no need for a preferred basis. (Given a Hamiltonian, eigenstates of the object system, initial state of the measurement device, and initial state of the observer system, we can check if Eq. (2b) holds true.) The following claim comes from author’s misconception. Secondly, suppose that the basis (φ0⊗Φ0, φ1⊗Φ1) is somehow selected. Then one can perhaps intuitively view the corresponding components of φ as describing a pair of independent worlds. But this intuitive interpretation goes beyond what the axioms justify; the axioms say nothing about the existence of multiple physical worlds corresponding to wavefunction components. As explained above, there is no objective multiple physical worlds corresponding to wavefunction components. The world is subjective and relative to each observer. Let us go on to the next claim: Thirdly, in any case, no physical meaning has been attached to the constants |a| and |b|. They are not to be interpreted as the probabilities that their respective branches are realized; this is the whole point of Everett’s proposal. It can not be said that a proportion |a| of the total number of worlds is in state φ0 ⊗ Φ0; there is nothing in the axioms to justify this claim. (Note that if the two worlds picture were justified, then each state would correspond to one world, and it must be explained why each measurement does not have probability 1 2 .) Nor can one argue that the probability of a particular observer finding herself in the world with state φ0 ⊗ Φ0 is |a| ; this conclusion again is unsupported by the axioms. The probability is not a branching rate into many-worlds, but is the relative frequency which is counted by the observer in each world [4]. It is easy to show that the observer who is described in each element of the superposition agrees that the relative frequency equals to
منابع مشابه
ar X iv : g r - qc / 9 70 40 54 v 1 1 9 A pr 1 99 7 The Nonlinear Quantum Gauge Theory – Superrelativity
A new type of nonlinear gauge quantum theory (superrelativity) has been proposed [1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6]. Such theory demands a radical reconstruction of the quantum field conception and spacetime structure, and this paves presumably way to the comprehension of the quantum nature of inertia.
متن کاملar X iv : g r - qc / 9 40 40 14 v 1 8 A pr 1 99 4 EXOTIC BLACK HOLES ∗
Black hole solutions can be used to shed light on general issues in General Relativity and Quantum Physics. Black–hole hair, entropy and naked singularities are considered here, along with some implications for the inflationary universe scenario.
متن کاملar X iv : g r - qc / 9 70 30 85 v 1 2 8 M ar 1 99 7 Gravity Quantized ( the high tension string )
A candidate theory of gravity quantized is reviewed.
متن کاملar X iv : g r - qc / 9 90 40 83 v 1 3 0 A pr 1 99 9 Black Holes and Wormholes in 2 + 1 Dimensions ∗
Vacuum Einstein theory in three spacetime dimensions is locally trivial, but admits many solutions that are globally different, particularly if there is a negative cosmological constant. The classical theory of such locally “anti-de Sitter” spaces is treated in an elementary way, using visualizable models. Among the objects discussed are black holes, spaces with multiple black holes, their hori...
متن کاملar X iv : s ol v - in t / 9 70 40 03 v 1 2 A pr 1 99 7 Convergent Normal Forms of Symmetric Dynamical Systems
It is shown that the presence of Lie-point-symmetries of (non-Hamiltonian) dynamical systems can ensure the convergence of the coordinate transformations which take the dynamical sytem (or vector field) into Poincaré-Dulac normal form.
متن کاملar X iv : g r - qc / 9 50 40 38 v 1 2 4 A pr 1 99 5 CLOCK AND CATEGORY : IS QUANTUM GRAVITY ALGE
We investigate the possibility that the quantum theory of gravity could be constructed discretely using algebraic methods. The algebraic tools are similar to ones used in constructing Topological Quantum Field theories. The algebraic structures are related to ideas about the reinterpretation of quantum mechanics in a general relativistic context.
متن کامل